Chapter 20  Micromega : tactics for solving arithmetics goals over ordered rings

Frédéric Besson and Evgeny Makarov

For using the tactics out-of-the-box, read Section 20.1. Section 20.2 presents some background explaining the proof principle for solving polynomials goals. Section 20.3 explains how to get a complete procedure for linear integer arithmetic.

20.1  The psatz tactic in a hurry

Load the Psatz module (Require Psatz.). This module defines the tactics: lia, psatzl D, and psatz D n where D is Z, Q or R and n is an optional integer limiting the proof search depth.

These tactics solve propositional formulas parameterised by atomic arithmetics expressions interpreted over a domain D ∈ {ℤ, ℚ, ℝ }. The syntax of the formulas is the following:

 F::=A ∣ P ∣ True ∣ False ∣ F1 ∧ F2 ∣ F1 ∨ F2 ∣ F1 ↔ F2 ∣ F1 → F2 ∣ ∼ F
 A::=p1 = p2 ∣  p1 > p2 ∣ p1 < p2 ∣ p1 ≥ p2 ∣ p1 ≤ p2 
 p::=c ∣ x ∣ −p ∣ p1 − p2 ∣ p1 + p2 ∣ p1 × p2 ∣ p ^ n

where c is a numeric constant, xD is a numeric variable and the operators −, +, ×, are respectively subtraction, addition, product, p ^n is exponentiation by a constant n, P is an arbitrary proposition. The following table details for each domain D ∈ {ℤ,ℚ,ℝ} the range of constants c and exponent n.

 ℝ 
  cZQ{R1, R0} 
  nZZnat

20.2  Positivstellensatz refutations

The name psatz is an abbreviation for positivstellensatz – literally positivity theorem – which generalises Hilbert’s nullstellensatz. It relies on the notion of Cone. Given a (finite) set of polynomials S, Cone(S) is inductively defined as the smallest set of polynomials closed under the following rules:

p ∈ S
p ∈ Cone(S)
    
p2 ∈ Cone(S)
   
p1 ∈ Cone(S)    p2 ∈ Cone(S)    ⑅ ∈ {+,*}
p1 ⑅ p2 ∈ Cone(S)

The following theorem provides a proof principle for checking that a set of polynomial inequalities do not have solutions2:

Theorem 1   Let S be a set of polynomials.
If
1 belongs to Cone(S) then the conjunction pS p≥ 0 is unsatisfiable.

A proof based on this theorem is called a positivstellensatz refutation. The tactics work as follows. Formulas are normalised into conjonctive normal form ∧i Ci where Ci has the general form (∧jSi pj ⑅ 0) → False) and ⑅ ∈ {>,≥,=} for D∈ {ℚ,ℝ} and ⑅ ∈ {≥, =} for ℤ. For each conjunct Ci, the tactic calls a oracle which searches for −1 within the cone. Upon success, the oracle returns a cone expression that is normalised by the ring tactic (see chapter 23) and checked to be −1.

To illustrate the working of the tactic, consider we wish to prove the following Coq goal.

Coq <   Goal forall x, -x^>= 0 -> x - 1 >= 0 -> False.

Such a goal is solved by intro x; psatz Z 2. The oracle returns the cone expression 2 × (x−1) + x−1×x−1 + x2 (polynomial hypotheses are printed in bold). By construction, this expression belongs to Cone({−x2, x −1}). Moreover, by running ring we obtain −1. By Theorem 1, the goal is valid.

The psatzl tactic

is searching for linear refutations using a fourier elimination3. As a result, this tactic explore a subset of the Cone defined as:

LinCone(S) =



 
p ∈ S
 αp × p 


 αp  are positive constants 



Basically, the deductive power of psatzl is the combined deductive power of ring_simplify and fourier.

The psatz tactic

explores the Cone by increasing degrees – hence the depth parameter n. In theory, such a proof search is complete – if the goal is provable the search eventually stops. Unfortunately, the external oracle is using numeric (approximate) optimisation techniques that might miss a refutation.

20.3   lia : the linear integer arithmetic tactic

The tactic lia offers an alternative to the omega and romega tactic (see Chapter 19). It solves goals that omega and romega do not solve, such as the following so-called omega nightmare [121].

Coq <   Goal forall x y, 
Coq <        27 <= 11 * x + 13 * y <= 45 -> 
Coq <        -10 <= 7 * x - 9 * y <= 4 ->   False.

The estimation of the relative efficiency of lia vs omega and romega is under evaluation.

High level view of lia.

Over ℝ, positivstellensatz refutations are a complete proof principle4. However, this is not the case over ℤ. Actually, positivstellensatz refutations are not even sufficient to decide linear integer arithmetics. The canonical exemple is 2 * x = 1 -> False which is a theorem of ℤ but not a theorem of ℝ. To remedy this weakness, the lia tactic is using recursively a combination of:

Cutting plane proofs

are a way to take into account the discreetness of ℤ by rounding up (rational) constants up-to the closest integer.

Theorem 2   Let p be an integer and c a rational constant.
  p ≥ c ⇒ p ≥ ⌈ c ⌉

For instance, from 2 * x = 1 we can deduce

By combining these two facts (in normal form) x − 1 ≥ 0 and −x ≥ 0, we conclude by exhibiting a positivstellensatz refutation (−1 ≡ x−1 + xCone({x−1,x})).

Cutting plane proofs and linear positivstellensatz refutations are a complete proof principle for integer linear arithmetic.

Case split

allow to enumerate over the possible values of an expression.

Theorem 3   Let p be an integer and c1 and c2 integer constants.
  c1 ≤ p ≤ c2 ⇒ 
 
x ∈ [c1,c2]
 p = x

Our current oracle tries to find an expression e with a small range [c1,c2]. We generate c2c1 subgoals which contexts are enriched with an equation e = i for i ∈ [c1,c2] and recursively search for a proof.


1
Sources and binaries can be found at https://projects.coin-or.org/Csdp
2
Variants deal with equalities and strict inequalities.
3
More efficient linear programming techniques could equally be employed
4
In practice, the oracle might fail to produce such a refutation.